It has now been a
year since equal marriage law came into effect in England and Wales. Across the
Atlantic, we may be on the cusp of marriage equality becoming a reality
nationwide in the United States. While over 70% of US citizens already live in
jurisdictions where same-sex couples can legally marry, there are over a dozen
states with same-sex marriage bans. In April this year, the US Supreme Court
will be reviewing same-sex marriage bans in four states (Kentucky, Michigan,
Ohio and Tennessee) and will decide, possibly once and for all, if the US
constitution’s principle of equal protection under law applies to lesbian and
gay US citizens, and their right to marry.
This would not
only be a victory for lesbian and gay activists but also, arguably, for
feminists. Although some would argue that feminists should be fighting to
abolish marriage rather than extending the right to marry, marriage equality
removes a form of discrimination based on a partner’s gender and, in one sense, transforms marriage into a genderless institution.
For the Religious
Right, this is a principal reason for opposing marriage equality. As a key
spokesperson for the UK anti-marriage equality group, the ‘Coalition for
Marriage’, stated in a video on their website:
“It would transform marriage into a genderless
institution. It would remove the core meaning of marriage, the complementary
union of a man and a woman. It is this institution alone that naturally gives
rise to children.”
It is clear then
that for equal marriage opponents (in the UK at least) arguments against
same-sex marriage are arguments for institutionalized heterosexuality and a
conception of marriage based on gender complementarity. Interestingly, from my own research on arguments against same-sex marriage in the UK
press, the notion of gender complementarity was not commonly used in this
explicit form. Rather, opponents used arguments that were ostensibly based on
facts rather than ideology. For example, opposition arguments appealed to
dictionary definitions of marriage (‘marriage is defined as being between a man
and a woman’) and to notions of tradition (‘marriage has always consisted of a
man and a woman’). Those who argue for equal marriage of course could argue the
opposite; that dictionary definitions can and do change. In fact, the Cambridge Online dictionary now defines marriage as “a legally
accepted relationship between two people”. Similarly, many would argue that the
institution of marriage is an evolving institution that has changed
dramatically over time. This perhaps exemplifies the Greek sophist Protagora’s
maxim, “In every question there are two sides to the argument, exactly opposite
to each other”.
The second argument
contained in the above quote from the ‘Coalition for Marriage’ spokesperson,
that (heterosexual) marriage is an institution that gives rise to children, was
commonly expressed by equal marriage opponents in the British press. Take the
following example where in a letter to a newspaper Editor, a British Member of
Parliament argues that marriage should not be extended to same-sex couples
because marriage is for the rearing of children:
Marriage is vital because it is where child rearing tends
to take place. Evidence recognises that married parents are good for
children and society. If gay couples are considered equally eligible for
marriage, even though gay relationships do not tend towards
child-raising and cannot by definition give a child a mother and a father, the
crucial understanding of what marriage is mainly for has been discarded (The
Times, 13 March, emphasis added)
Rhetorical social
psychologist Michael Billig suggests that arguments often contain the seeds of
their own negation. For example, when making a generalization, a speaker will
typically qualify these to acknowledge the existence of exceptions. By describing marriage as where child rearing
tends to take place, same-sex
relationships as not tending towards
child-raising and child-rearing as what marriage is mainly for, the above argument contains within it the seeds of its own
counter argument i.e. that not all children are born within marriage, that some
same-sex couples do raise children and that not all heterosexual married
couples have children, so it cannot be what marriage is for entirely. As Billig
notes, any act of generalization can always be potentially negated by a
particularization. Furthermore, if ‘married parents are good for children’ (and
one may wish to question the supposed evidence upon which such claims are made)
then one might ask why marriage should not also be good for the children of
same-sex parents. Of course, what is partially hidden (or implicit) within this
argument is the assertion that it is heterosexual parents (with ‘complementary
genders’) which provide both mothers and fathers that are good for children,
not simply married parents.
But why not just
come out and say that heterosexuality is better for children and society? Perhaps
because the idea that marriage is good for children and society is typically
seen as uncontroversial (although many feminists may take issue with this). To
say that heterosexual parents are better for children is a more contentious
statement, and one that is flatly refuted by a summary of the evidence by the American Psychological Association. Furthermore, the way that it is framed
here is more guarded against accusations of prejudice.
Posted by: Dr Adam Jowett
Lecturer in Psychology
Department of Psychology and Behavioural Sciences (JS259)
Coventry University, United Kingdom
No comments:
Post a Comment